Initial Observations by CHA Member Ethicists on the
Vatican Document
Shortly after this document appeared we solicited
comments from some of our system ethicists. We
combined them with our own observations and grouped
them under three categories. We hope that these initial
thoughts will stimulate more reflection on the meaning
and importance of this document. We will be happy to
publish other comments in our next issue.
-C.B. and N.B.H.
On December 10, 2018, the Congregation for
the Doctrine of the Faith issued a new
document on the liceity of hysterectomy in
certain cases.1
This document is a response to questions about
certain “extreme cases” in which the uterus is in
an irreversible condition such that a pregnancy
will result in a spontaneous abortion before the
fetus is able to arrive at a viable state.
OBSERVATIONS AND QUESTIONS
The questions behind the dubium and the CDF
response are complicated. It seems that the
document makes some new distinctions. It also
raises some new questions. We have solicited comments from a number of ethicists and have
integrated their comments into this essay under
three general categories: questions about
methodology, clinical questions and questions
about language and meaning. They are
intended to facilitate dialogue and to help
achieve consensus on the correct interpretation.
METHODOLOGICAL QUESTIONS
The new document responds to three
questions: a) Is it licit to remove a damaged or
diseased uterus in order to counter “an
immediate serious threat” to the mother, even
if it results in permanent sterility? b) Is it licit to
remove a uterus that is not in itself a “present
risk to the life and health of the woman,” but in
order to prevent a “possible future danger”
deriving from conception? c) Is it licit to
substitute tubal ligation, “also called ‘uterine
isolation’ for the hysterectomy,” because it is
simpler and less serious, and because the
resulting sterility might be reversed?
For two of the questions, the new document
affirms teaching found in the 1993 Response of the CDF to “Questions Proposed Concerning
‘Uterine Isolation’ and Related Matters.”2
Regarding (a), it uses traditional double effect
reasoning to affirm that it is licit to perform a
hysterectomy to remedy an immediate threat
such as endometriosis or uterine cancer.
Regarding (c), it affirms that a tubal ligation,
even if described in terms of uterine isolation, is
still “intrinsically illicit as an end and a means.”
With (b), however, it takes a methodological
turn and allows a hysterectomy when the uterus
is deemed to be incapable of bringing a
pregnancy to term. In this case, hysterectomy
does not “regard”3 sterilization and is entirely
different than the “uterine isolation” question
to which they responded in July of 1993.
However, this still seems to beg the question: If
a hysterectomy in the cases referred to is not
equivalent to a direct sterilization, what is its
purpose? As one ethicist asks: “What would be
the purpose of removing the uterus in this
instance? It’s not cancerous or diseased, so it’s
not threatening her health or the life of the
fetus. There aren’t fibroids so it’s not a precancerous condition and it isn’t causing her
pain or suffering. It’s just sitting there and
would be fine if left alone.” The purpose
seems to be to prevent future pregnancy which
in all likelihood could not come to term.
Principle of Double Effect: The new document
continues to tolerate sterilization as an
unintended effect of a therapeutic action (e.g.,
to treat uterine cancer or endometriosis) on the
basis of the principle of double effect because
the two effects – therapy for the disease and
loss of fertility – are inseparable. Yet it allows a
hysterectomy because of an existing, virtual
sterility due to the condition of the uterus. In
this case, however, the two effects are not inseparably connected. The removal of the
uterus, which is not undertaken with a
therapeutic intent, is done in order to prevent a
future pregnancy.
The document suggests that hysterectomy is
permissible because the uterus is damaged or
diseased beyond repair and is therefore “unable
to fulfill [its] procreative function.” Since the
uterus is unable to fill this role, procreation is
impossible so the hysterectomy is not “against
procreation.”
However, it also says “we are not dealing with a
defective, or risky functioning of the
reproductive organs.” Does this mean that
hysterectomy is not allowed if the uterus is
defective or functioning badly in a way that may
harm the mother, but only if it is so thoroughly
compromised that it is a risk to the fetus?
How certain is certain? The document does not
indicate exactly what might constitute the
extreme cases in which a hysterectomy is
permissible, but it does acknowledge the need
for a clinical judgment and requires “the highest
degree of certainty” that the uterus cannot
support a pregnancy to term.
There are two issues here. First, physicians
agree that “certainty” is difficult to come by in
most medical matters. One ethicist noted the
necessarily prudential nature of this judgment:
“There are conditions in which this judgment
might attempt to be applied, such as repeated
damage from C-sections, congenital
malformations (bicornate uterus), antiphospholipid antibodies, etc. All of these could
conceivably (pardon the pun) result in multiple
miscarriages, without being able to declare with
the highest degree of medical certainty that
such a result would be inevitable in an individual case, and it must perforce occur prior
to viability. The present responsum requires
and assumes the presence of all these
conditions. However, all medical
prognostication is really just an exercise in
probabilities – certainty is extremely hard to
come by, and rarely possible.” Second, it is
unclear whether the “highest” certainty called
for is the same as “moral certainty” which has
been the traditional criterion for action in cases
of doubt or if it is a more rigorous standard.
The role of circumstances. Another issue is the
relevance of circumstances. Traditional moral
reasoning allows circumstances a determinative
role in the moral quality of the action only
when the action does not involve intrinsic evil.
However, Dr. Amy Warner and Sr. Patricia
Talone suggest the complex circumstances of
time, geography, finances and personal issues
that are part of clinical judgments are very
important to good medicine especially when the
issue is a sustained medical event like
pregnancy. Shouldn’t the ability to pre-empt
complications and travel distance from medical
resources figure into the equation if we are
virtually certain of future outcome?
CLINICAL QUESTIONS
The most important clinical issue is the
disparity between medical standards of care4
which call for the most effective, safest, and
least invasive treatment possible, and the
requirements of our moral tradition. At the
moment, our understanding of pre-emptive
sterilizations as intrinsically illicit runs counter
to best practice because it is often the safest
and least invasive option.
Another issue is anatomical. Both documents
speak as if the uterus and fallopian tubes are totally separate organs such that it is
permissible to remove one but not the other.
Medical embryology suggests they develop as
one. As Talone and Warner say elsewhere in
this issue:
Fallopian tubes, also called uterine
tubes are not distinct from, but a
part of the uterus. It is important to
note that the uterus develops
embryologically from the fusion of
the two paramesonephric ducts
which fuse in the midline to form
the uterine body and fundus. The
free ends of these ducts remain as
appendages forming the uterine, or
fallopian, tubes.5
This is a very important point. If the uterus
and the fallopian tubes are both part of a single
organ, then doesn’t it seem more logical (and
clinically sound) to remove as little of the organ
as possible? Wouldn’t that suggest a partial or
total salpingectomy rather than a hysterectomy
if they both accomplish the same purpose?
Clinical circumstances. We have already noted the
methodological importance of circumstances.
They are also important in clinical judgments.
Warner and Talone note specifically clinical
circumstances like the patient’s condition,
blood pressure, medication side effects, as well
as time, place, and available resources. These
circumstances often determine the
appropriateness of one course of treatment
over another. Is there not a way that we can
take greater account of circumstance from a
moral perspective as well?
LANGUAGE AND TERMINOLOGY
QUESTIONS
The document notes that the “malice of
sterilization” (here referring to a tubal ligation
or “uterine isolation”) is rooted in the “refusal
of children” and is “an act against the bonum
prolis.” The removal of a uterus which is
unable to bring a pregnancy is not a refusal of
children the document maintains, because no
complete pregnancy is possible. However, it
does not seem that a salpingectomy in the same
situation is necessarily a refusal of children,
either. In fact, in the cases described by Warner
and Talone, the couple may sincerely WANT
more children, but deem it impossible or too
risky.
There is also some question about whether this
new document redefines procreation. Our
traditional understanding is based upon a
presumption that a unique human person exists
from the moment of conception. Even
though it is physically impossible for the egg
and sperm to unite and result in a new
organism in the absence of a uterus, the
document’s understanding of “procreation”
seems to imply that procreation involves
ovulation, fertilization, implantation, gestation
and delivery. If that is so, it seems to give full
protection only to children that are born. Even
though fertilization is impossible without a
uterus, since the sperm must travel through the
uterus to fertilize the egg in the uterine tube,
doesn’t the fact that conception could take
place if the uterus were left in place indicate
that the intent is to prevent conception?
Others have raised similar questions. Jeanne
Smits says the document “rests on skewed
definitions of the words ‘procreation’ and
‘sterilization. ’” The classic definition of procreation, Smits says, “is here destroyed by a
stroke of the pen.”6
The Couple to Couple League raises similar
questions, saying “this reasoning on the part of
the CDF is somewhat surprising.” Both groups
suggest that the document confuses, rather than
clarifies, the matter. Dr. Philip Schepens, a
former member of the Pontifical Academy for
Life, says the Response is “unnecessary and at
the same time unnecessarily creates
confusion.”7
One final point about language is that the
document does not use the terms “intrinsic
evil” or “intrinsically immoral,” terms that have
appeared in other documents, including the
Ethical and Religious Directives.8 Instead they
speak of “intrinsically illicit” and “morally
illicit.” These terms may be equivalent to “evil”
and “immoral,” but some of us wonder
whether the shade of difference is significant. Is
the choice of language lowering stakes in some
way?9
This document is important because it takes
explicit account of advances in medical science
that enable us to diagnose causes and anticipate
outcomes in a way that was not possible in the
past. Until modern times, there was little
understanding of what caused miscarriages or
failure to conceive in the first place. Can our
moral reasoning find a way to acknowledge
these advances?
Overall, the document seems to open the door
to further discussion, but it also raises as many
questions as it answers. It seems to ignore
important clinical facts, such as the connection
between the uterus and the uterine tubes, and
in our view does not give adequate attention to our responsibility to prevent foreseeable future
harms to mother and child.
ENDNOTES
1 Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, “Response to a
Question on the Liceity of a Hysterectomy in Certain Cases,”
December 10, 2018.
2 “Responses to Questions Proposed Concerning Uterine Isolation
and Related Matters,” July 31, 1994.
http://www.vatican.va/roman_curia/congregations/cfaith/docum
ents/rc_con_cfaith_doc_31071994_uterine-isolation_en.html See
also “Reply of the Sacred Congregation for the Doctrine of the
Faith on Sterilization in Catholic Hospitals” (Quaecumque Sterilizatio)
March 13, 1975.
3 “Regard” is not common English usage in this case. The Italian
phrase is “perche non si tratta di sterilizzazione” and the French is
“il ne s’agit pas de stérillisation” both of which have a clearer
connotation of “has nothing to do with.” If the intent is to
distinguish the case they cite from sterilization, a better choice
would have been “does not constitute” or “does not involve”
sterilization.
4 While standards of care are often used to assess allegations of
medical malpractice, they are also guidelines for the best treatment,
given current evidence. See Brian K. Cooke, Elizabeth
Worsham and Gary M. Reisfield, “The Elusive Standard of Care,”
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law
Online (September 2017) 45 (3) 358-364.
5 Thomas W. Sadler, Langman’s Medical Embryology, 13th edition,
(Philadelphia: Wolters, Kluwer Health, 2015) 266. Sadler’s view is
affirmed in Moore's The Developing Human: Clinically Oriented
Embryology, 10th edition (Elsevier, 2015) and Schoenwolf, Larsen's
Human Embryology, 5th edition (Elsevier, 2014).
6 Jeanne Smits is the editor of the right-wing French periodical
Présent and a frequent critic of Pope Francis. “Do the Vatican’s
New Guidelines on Hysterectomy Open a Door to Contraception
and Abortion?” LifeSite News (January 18, 2019). The document,
she says, employs “strange reasoning indeed, insofar as the removal
of the uterus is well and truly performed in order to ‘impeded the
functioning of the reproductive organs…deliberately preventing
that from happening in itself constitutes sterilization.” She also
says that “the response “if read logically, appears to consider a
conceived child who is not viable as not being the fruit of the true
procreation.” (https://lifesitenews.com/opinion/do-vaticans-newguidelines-on-hysterectomy-open-a-door-to-contraception-andabortion). Accessed January 27, 2019. (On January 30, the website
said the article “no longer exists or has moved.”)
7 Forest Hempden, “What the New Vatican Document says About
Hysterectomy,” Couple to Couple League, January 3, 2019.
(https://ccli.org/2019/01/01/what-the-new-vatican-documentsays-about-hysterectomy/ ). Accessed January 27, 2019.
8 United States Conference of Catholic Bishops, Ethical and Religious
Directives for Catholic Health Care Services, 6th ed. (Washington DC:
USCCB, 2018)
9 In sacramental theology, there is a significant difference between
“illicit” and “invalid.” The former connotes a violation of law,
doing something not allowed, but still sacramentally valid. The
latter means that, to use a mechanical analogy, just doesn’t work
because of some inherent defect, such as inappropriate matter (e.g.,
attempting to consecrate a bottle of chocolate milk instead of a
chalice of wine). Is the use of illicit here rather than immoral
analagous to the sacramental use, where licit is a matter of law, and
valid refers to sacramental effectiveness?