Schuklenk, Udo, and Ricardo
Smalling."Why medical professionals
have no moral claim to conscientious
objection accommodation in liberal
democracies." Journal of medical ethics 43,
no. 4 (2017): 234-240.
Udo Schuklenk and Ricardo Smalling
argue that in liberal democracies medical
professionals have no moral claim to
conscientiously object to the provision of
services that are within the scope of professional
practice. Accommodating conscientious
objection has numerous significant issues. First,
we cannot determine the truth of the beliefs
that are motivating the conscientious objection
and we cannot determine that those beliefs are
genuinely held. Because of this, any attempts
to draw lines between objections that should be
accommodated and those that should not will
be arbitrary. Second, conscientious objection
disregards the needs of patients and creates
inefficiency and inequity in accessing healthcare.
Consider a woman in a rural area where
abortion is legal, but there are a limited amount
of providers willing to provide this service. This
may result in the woman having to “depend on
the goodwill of volunteering doctors” (237). It
is unavoidable that conscience claims will result
in suboptimal access to healthcare and arbitrary service standards. Third, accommodating
conscientious objection will also result in an
inequitable workload for unobjecting doctors
and it is unclear why this unfair burden
should be accepted. As medical professionals
voluntarily enter their profession, they should
be prepared to offer the services that are within
the scope of medical practice. If they are not
able to offer those services, they do not belong
in the profession.
Schuklenk and Smalling’s argument provides
a compelling account of how accommodating
conscientious objection can result in unfair
harms for patients. The potential harms
patients, especially patients from vulnerable
communities, may face should be addressed
in all accounts of conscientious objection.
It is important to consider ways potential
harms to patients can be mitigated. While
Schuklenk and Smalling’s argument succeeds
in highlighting potential harms that may result
from accommodating conscientious objection,
it operates on a misguided understanding of
medical professionalism. Their conception of
professionalism requires that an individual’s
religious beliefs be relegated to the private
sphere. They wrongly assume that a person can
disregard their own moral starting point and
utilize only secular neutral reason. However,
secular reason, like religious reason, is not
without tradition. Further, professional identity is not formed in a vacuum. It is the
combination of professional and private values.
Schuklenk and Smalling overlook how the
private values of professionals can help to
morally correct medicine when it strays into
morally objectionable territory. This is not
to say that all conscience claims should be
accommodated regardless of the moral reasons
for them because of their potential to help
medicine morally self-correct. This is only to
say that there is more value to accommodating
conscientious objection than Schuklenk and
Smalling acknowledge.
Symons, Xavier. "Conscientious objection
in health care: Why the professional duty
argument is unconvincing." The Journal
of Medicine and Philosophy: A Forum for
Bioethics and Philosophy of Medicine 47, no.
4 (2022): 549-557.
Xavier Symons responds to what he calls the
Professional Duty Argument (PDA), which
claims that doctors should set their moral or
religious beliefs aside when they are in conflict
with what the relevant professional associations
have deemed a part of good medical practice.
As the enter their profession voluntarily, they
should be prepared to offer what has been
determined to be a part of good medical
practice. Under the PDA, accommodation of
conscientious objection should be very limited,
if allowed at all because it is at odds with
professional duty. Symons raises two objection
to the PDA—the fallibility objection and the
professional discretion objection. The fallibility
objection acknowledges that professional
codes of conduct are epistemically fallible
ways of determining what is good medicine.
Accommodating conscience claims can provide
a check on the law and professional associations that guide the moral conduct of doctors by
allowing individual providers to determine
whether the guidance of the law and the
profession is ethical. The professional discretion
objection recognizes the need for medical
professionals to be afforded the discretionary
space to determine what is best for a patient in
a particular situation. The PDA disregards that
medical judgments involve both technical and
moral considerations. By heavily restricting the
discretionary space of the medical professional,
we are impeding their ability to better respond
to particular needs of each individual patient
and act with moral integrity. While this article
provides a strong critique of the Professional
Duty Argument, it does not consider what
limits, if any, should be placed on the
professional discretionary space.
Sulmasy, Daniel P. "Conscience, tolerance,
and pluralism in health care." Theoretical
medicine and bioethics 40, no. 6 (2019):
507-521.
Daniel Sulmasy addresses the issue of “how
a tolerant, pluralistic, liberal democracy”
should handle cases where a professional
has an ethical objection to providing a
morally controversial service that is legal
and is supported by at least some members
of the profession. Sulmasy claims that this
is not necessarily an issue of conscience, but
an issue of how much discretionary space
professionals should be afforded to “foster
the proper relationship among the state, the
market, and the professions in a flourishing,
pluralistic, liberal democracy” and how much
discretionary space should be afforded to “meet
the basic standards of tolerance that all citizens
can expect in a flourishing, pluralistic, liberal
democracy” (515). While professions establish the goals and ethics of their practice alongside
society, there must be discretionary space for
individual professionals. In the same way it is
not desirable for political powers to infringe
upon the discretionary space of a profession,
professions should aim to not infringe upon
the discretionary space of individuals. As
professional judgment has both technical and
moral elements, it is important to respect the
discretionary space of individuals to determine
what is in the scope of good medicine. Sulmasy
argues “forcing individuals to violate their
deeply held moral beliefs regarding practices
that are not central to their professional
activities as a condition of practicing that
profession, when the common good is not
threatened, is intolerant” (517-518). Tolerance
requires that a profession tolerate a diversity of
personal characteristics and a diversity of beliefs
and practices. However, there are limits to a
person’s claims of tolerance. While refusing to
perform an action that is immoral has a claim
to tolerance, refusing to treat someone you
disagree with or whose personal characteristics
you do not like does not have a claim to
tolerance.
Sulmasy offers a much needed conceptual
clarity to important terms in the conscientious
objection debate (e.g., conscience,
conscientious action, professional medical
judgment, conscientious objection, conscience
clauses, civil disobedience, and tolerance).
As “the bar for not tolerating diverse views
and practices, on a Lockean analysis, is quite
high—tolerating the view must substantially
undermine the common good,” we are left to
consider whether difficult cases of conscientious
objection, such as those involving gender-affirming care, rise to the level of substantially
undermining the common good (518).
SYNTHESIS
While common arguments against
accommodating conscientious objection
involve the privileging of secularly understood
medical professionalism that is at odds with
some religious traditions, these arguments
remind us of the need to consider how we
can better care for vulnerable patients and
limit potential harms they may experience.
As Catholic healthcare continues to care for
patients of diverse backgrounds in an evolving
sociopolitical landscape, we should be mindful
of how formation efforts are occurring within
a particular sociopolitical landscape. As these
articles highlight, it is important that we
consider what professional identity consists of
and what the limits of professional discretion
are.
MARISSA D. ESPINOZA
Saint Louis University
St. Louis, Missouri
[email protected]