Normothermic Regional Perfusion (NRP) is a
category of organ preservation techniques that
have been used in procurement for controlled
donation after circulatory-determined death
(cDCD) for more than a decade. The general
concept, after removing life-sustaining
treatments and technologies from a donor
patient and allowing for the appropriate standoff period to declare death, involves regionally
reperfusing vital organs inside the dead donor
before procurement by applying extracorporeal
membrane oxygenation (ECMO). Variations
according to technique and organs procured
notwithstanding, NRP shows promise for
increasing organ availability in the United
States, particularly for livers and hearts,1
as has
been the case in other countries.2
While patient
outcomes and organ viability are important for
determinations of ethical appropriateness, the
field is rapidly evolving; this work addresses
ethical concerns given a medical or resource
allocation advantage.
There are two commonly cited ethical concerns
with NRP. First, reperfusing vital organs
in situ raises concerns that this method of
procurement violates the Dead Donor Rule
(DDR) in that circulation of oxygenated
blood, previously deemed irreversibly lost, is
restored to a limited number of organs by
region. Second, after death has been declared
and before initiating ECMO, all NRP techniques occlude potential blood flow to
the brain – either singly or grouped with other
organs. Some question whether this action,
especially directly occluding flow to the brain
only, intentionally hastens death or even
creates a “brain death” situation. If even one of
these concerns is validated, then NRP may be
morally illicit.
This work explores both concerns by examining
the actions of regional reperfusion in situ
and occlusion of blood flow to the brain in
the cDCD circumstance and demonstrates
that NRP can be an ethical option for organ
procurement; it also incorporates discussion
of circumstances in the U.S. that have led to
mistrust in organ procurement processes. This
work relies on Entwistle’s comprehensive
analysis and others for technical reference and
offers additional considerations for Catholic
health care.3
CIRCUMSTANCES
The clinical circumstances leading to cDCD
are generally not equivocal. Although the
patient does not meet the neurologic criteria
to declare death (BD/DNC), medical and
ethical standards indicate that withdrawing
life sustaining treatment is appropriate, and
this decision is separate and distinct from
the decision to move forward with organ procurement. In addition, the patient, or
the patient’s surrogate decision maker, has
authorized and intends to donate organs. Once
the decision has been made to withdraw life-sustaining treatments, the do not resuscitate
order written, and medical interventions
withdrawn, reinitiating life sustaining
treatments would be medically and morally
inappropriate.
DETERMINATION OF DEATH
In the United States, The Uniform
Determination of Death Act (UDDA)4
stipulates that the determination of death must
be made in accordance with accepted medical
standards and provides two pathways for death
to be determined: (1) irreversible cessation of
circulatory and respiratory functions, or (2)
irreversible cessation of all functions of the
entire brain, including the brain stem. Debate
regarding substituting the word permanent for
irreversible notwithstanding, the conjunction
“or” is key.
Neither pathway is prioritized over the other,
and, although only one pathway must be
satisfied, the whole person is dead. While
much emphasis historically has been placed
on the establishment of death by neurologic
criteria as ethically sufficient for satisfying
the DDR before organ procurement, it seems
that today some ethicists prefer BD/DNC as
being more morally legitimate than cDCD; but
medical and legal standards say otherwise. If a
person is declared dead by circulatory criteria,
that person’s brain is also dead by the same
criteria because circulation to the whole body,
including the brain, has ceased.5,6 The person is
dead. This is one of the reasons that the term
“brain death” is so unfortunate – because it gives the impression that only the brain is dead when
the person is dead by BD/DNC.
Within the Catholic tradition, Pope John
Paul II condoned the concept of death
determination by neurologic criteria, but he did
not disavow death determination by cessation
of circulatory and respiratory functions. Rather,
he stated in the context of organ donation:
"With regard to the parameters used today for
ascertaining death - whether the 'encephalic'
signs or the more traditional cardio-respiratory
signs - the Church does not make technical
decisions… the criterion adopted in more
recent times for ascertaining the fact of death,
namely the complete and irreversible cessation
of all brain activity, if rigorously applied,
does not seem to conflict with the essential
elements of a sound anthropology. Therefore
a health worker professionally responsible for
ascertaining death can use these criteria in each
individual case as the basis for arriving at that
degree of assurance in ethical judgement which
moral teaching describes as 'moral certainty'".7
The notion that neurologic criteria of death
must always be met to procure vital organs is
inconsistent with the Holy See statement.
DOES OCCLUDING POTENTIAL BLOOD
FLOW TO THE BRAIN AFTER A PATIENT
DIES CHANGE THE KIND OF DEATH THAT
HAS OCCURRED OR INTENTIONALLY
CAUSE DEATH?
Some clinicians and at least one professional
society8
have advanced the notion that
occluding potential blood flow to the brain
after death and before ECMO essentially converts the circulatory-determined death to
death by neurologic criteria. In addition to
being illogical and unnecessary, this language
is unhelpful for Catholics because it makes
death the goal of an action and implies that
the donor may not be dead yet. Dead people
cannot die. As the Holy Father stated regarding
determining death with certainty:
"…the death of the person is a single event,
consisting in the total disintegration of that
unitary and integrated whole that is the
personal self. It results from the separation of
the life-principle (or soul) from the corporal
reality of the person. The death of the person,
understood in this primary sense, is an event
which no scientific technique or empirical
method can identify directly."9
Medical standards change over time because
the profession is constantly learning. Medical
professionals rely on markers of death that
have been demonstrated to be reliable, if not
infallible, and imprecise language decreases
confidence in those standards. A dead person
cannot re-die; only a living person can die.
And, if death is a single event, then one person
should not be considered more dead than
another person who has been declared dead
by generally accepted medical, moral and legal
standards.
Taken to its logical end, the concern for
Catholics around this language is not that
resuscitation is avoided, which is consistent
with stated wishes, medical standards and the
Catholic moral tradition. The concern, rather,
is that this language provides reason to question
whether the patient, in fact, might not be
dead, and occluding flow to the brain would
then be killing. Imprecise language, while not necessarily indicative of truth, undermines
confidence in medical standards and moral
liceity of all cDCD. The whole notion smacks
of conflicting interests and procurement slight-of-hand. Transparency, consistency and careful
and precise language around the circumstances
and process for declaring death is important.
WHY OCCLUDE FLOW TO THE BRAIN
BEFORE APPLYING ECMO?
There are good reasons to occlude flow to
the dead donor’s brain before initiating
ECMO, and they have to do with the kind
of intervention ECMO is and the intentions
and responsibilities of stakeholders. ECMO
is generally considered a life-sustaining and
even resuscitative intervention, but in NRP,
ECMO is an organ preservation procedure.
Circumstances matter; there is not – and
should not be – any intention to resuscitate
the dead donor. The intention of the medical
team in occluding flow to the brain before
initiating ECMO is to avoid resuscitating or
even appearing to try to resuscitate the dead
donor during organ preservation and testing.
Procurement teams may express this in other
ways, like stating that they are respecting the
dead donor. It is the ethics community’s job to
sort through clinician’s statements and meaning
and offer guidance through ethical exploration
and discourse.
The Permanence Principle has been utilized
in countries where the definition of death
following cessation of cardiorespiratory
function is primarily based on brain perfusion
(e.g., United Kingdom10), and it allows for
reperfusion in situ of organs that will be
procured using NRP as long as the brain is
not reperfused.11 This stipulation is logical considering that death, so defined, has just been
permitted to occur. The question is whether
the same principle should apply in the U.S. or
in Catholic health care, where the language
defining the same reality of death is different.
Regarding circulatory death, Gardiner and
colleagues note that, “The main justification for
adopting permanent cessation over irreversible
cessation… is that, in the great majority of
cases, it is not ethically appropriate to attempt
CPR or ECMO on such patients.”12 This aligns
with Bernat’s observation that “permanence is
a perfect surrogate indicator for irreversibility”
because spontaneous return of circulation will
not happen and no intervention will be made
to make it happen.13
The first and primary decision in the cDCD
pathway is to withdraw treatments and
technologies based on a wholistic assessment
of clinical condition, standards, prognosis,
treatment appropriateness and patient wishes.
Although clinicians may have the technical
ability to reverse the loss of cardiorespiratory
function temporarily, it has already been
determined that they do not have the ability
to restore the patient’s health. Resuscitating a
person from whom life-sustaining treatments
have intentionally been withdrawn in these
clinical circumstances is illogical, irresponsible
and possibly illegal.
The debate has been ongoing for more than
fifteen years in America. The American
College of Physicians approves of using
“permanent” in the cDCD domain but opposes
in the BD/DNC domain.14 The American
Academy of Neurology has transitioned
to using the new verbiage in BD/DNC
standards.15 The USCCB and NCBC strongly stated opposition to substituting “permanent”
for “irreversible” in brain death determinations,
but they were less clear about their concerns
in the cDCD realm, stating that this was a
concern “during controlled circulatory death,”
rather than using the word “after.”16 It is true
that occluding flow to the brain during the
stand-off period could be hastening death, but
the same cannot be true after death has been
declared unless the whole cDCD construct is
illicit.
To be clear, this work only considers the use of
the word “permanent” in the cDCD domain.
If removing a heart after controlled circulatory-determined death for preservation outside of
the donor’s body (direct procurement and
perfusion) is not hastening death, then how
could occluding blood vessels between the heart
and brain have that result? These two actions
have essentially the same effect on potential
blood flow. The debate about verbiage is
important and ongoing, but it should not
distract from this issue; occluding blood vessels
to the brain in a patient who is already dead
does not hasten death.
DOES REGIONAL REPERFUSION IN SITU
AFTER CIRCULATORY-DETERMINED
DEATH RESTORE CIRCULATORY AND
RESPIRATORY FUNCTION OF THE DEAD
PERSON?
After death is determined by circulatory criteria,
quickly reestablishing perfusion to the organs
to be procured for transplantation optimizes
future organ viability. NRP utilizes the dead
donor’s body as the instrument of this activity
by regions, and there are specific advantages
to this methodology. In the United Kingdom, where the Permanence Rule applies, reestablishing perfusion in the body but not in
the brain conforms to ethical standards because
of the way death is defined. How could the
definition of circulatory-determined death in
the U.S. be understood in a similarly useful
way?
The word “function” warrants interpretive
consideration. Is respiratory function (the
natural purpose of the respiratory system17)
to move air in and out of the body, or is it to
oxygenate and ventilate blood? Similarly, is
circulatory function to move blood through
unintegrated portions of the body, or is the
natural purpose of the circulatory system to
perfuse the essential organs to be alive? Can
there be circulatory function without perfusing
the brain? The concept of regional perfusion
is important because it does not allow for
integrated function of the circulatory system;
that is, at least one essential organ is not being
perfused. ECMO can be used to perfuse and
preserve organs by body region selectively. If
the heart, lungs and brain are all reperfused
together, ECMO could easily qualify as
a (medically and ethically inappropriate)
resuscitative measure, but circulatory function
is not achieved without the brain.
Another practical consideration is whether
perfusing the brain would serve to meet
any transplant objectives. The brain is not transplantable and will not be procured, so
there is no reason to perfuse it. So, given
the medical circumstances of the decision to
withdraw life-sustaining treatments, the morally
and legally valid declaration of death, the
intentions of the patient to donate organs and
the transplant team to preserve organs and not
resuscitate the patient, and the absence of any
future use of the brain in transplantation, there
should be no moral issue with occluding flow
to the brain and then initiating ECMO for
organ preservation in the dead donor’s body.
The concept of regional perfusion begs further
analysis. The difference in perfusing the brain
and the legs, for example, is that the legs do not
contain vital organs, and the legs do not define
death. Because the legs do not contain vital
organs perfusion is not necessary to achieve the
medical goals, and since they are not involved
in defining death, there is greater latitude in
perfusion decisions. Clinical circumstances
and professional judgment determine whether
to perfuse them. While techniques vary by
procurement goals, donor condition, clinician
training, and resources, procurement teams
approach regional perfusion decisions with
intention.18 They are not applying ECMO in
a manner consistent with a resuscitation of a
person. See Table 1 for additional, though not
comprehensive, considerations about regional
perfusion.
TABLE 1: REGIONAL PERFUSION CONSIDERATIONS FOR NRP
Region | Vital
Organs | Defines
Death | Transplantable
Vital Organs | Regional
Perfusion
Details | Perfusion
Benefit | Recommendation |
Head | Y | Y | N | Avoids donor
resuscitation.
Always
excluded.
Procedure near
cannulation site
prior to ECMO
in TA NRP | N | Do not perfuse |
Upper
Extremities
| N | N | N | If perfused,
could result
in collateral
circulation to
brain | N | Do not perfuse |
Thorax | Y | Y | Y | Occluded for
abdominal only
NRP:
- also occludes
head/UE
- additional
procedure
on thoracic
aorta
| Y | Perfuse for heart
and/or lung
procurement |
Abdomen | Y | N | Y | Not occluded:
- location of
most vital
organs
- chemical
advantage
| Y | Perfuse per
procurement
goals and clinical
circumstances |
MOVING FORWARD IN CATHOLIC HEALTH
CARE
Decisions to adopt clinical practices and
technologies are not made in a vacuum. That
is, Catholic moral reasoning is applied within
the U.S. construct of health care policy and
medical standards. In recent years, trust in
organ procurement has deteriorated largely due
to system-based challenges. It is important
that Catholic hospitals recognize these
challenges and engage with Organ Procurement
Organizations (OPO) and policy makers to
improve relationships and align work toward
optimizing organ availability and resources to
serve humanity.
Recent Center for Medicare and Medicaid
Services (CMS) OPO certification changes
have created pressure on OPOs that has led to
more aggressive enforcement of first-person
authorization and forced hospitals to take
sides.19 While the U.S. purports having an
opt-in system, first-person authorization may
be interpreted in ways that challenge whether
the donor understands what their authorization
means. First-person authorization has little in
common with informed consent. Indicating
a desire to be an organ donor in an advance
medical directive, while somewhat more
meaningful than checking a box while getting
a driver’s license, could be achieved with little
or no conversation; families, who know and
love the dying person, feel responsible. In these
circumstances, the act of love that Catholics
understand organ donation to be may even
devolve into a legal battle. Considering that
trust in health care is already low in America,
this is not helpful.
Another issue, translation issues aside, is that
different countries use different words to define death. Many authors cited in this work urge
international agreement in defining death, but
agreement is difficult to reach across cultural,
religious and legal boundaries. At a minimum,
engaging and understanding circumstances,
intentions and actions with precise language in
communities of practice will promote trust and
alignment.
Strategy and transparency are also important
to promote trust. Changing too many variables
at once is not helpful because correlations and
causality become unclear. At present, it is best
not to shorten the stand-off period to less than
five minutes in NRP. In addition, identifying,
owning and communicating areas of
uncertainty to the broader medical community
will improve alignment. There are additional
issues related to facility resource utilization and
clinical accountability that significantly affect
organ procurement, and OPO agreements
should be reviewed and adjusted, as needed and
regularly.
Organ donation has always been received
with suspicion because it attempts to achieve
a moral good that exists at the boundaries
of anthropological and religious values.
Still, much has been achieved. NRP is one
procurement category that evokes many valid
questions for clinicians, religious leaders,
ethicists and families, and these questions
should be addressed systematically and
transparently. For now, moving forward
is possible if all parties agree on intentions,
objectives, standards and moral constraints.
KELLY STUART, MD, MPH, MTS, MSNDR
Vice President, Ethics
Bon Secours Mercy
Health
Richmond, Virginia
ENDNOTES
- Chetan Pasrija, et al. “Normothermic Regional
Perfusion for Donation after Circulatory Death Donors,”
Transplantation 28 no. 2 (2023): 71-75
- Stephen O’Neill, et al., “The British Transplantation
Society Guidelines on Organ Donation from Deceased
Donors after Circulatory Death,” Transplantation
Reviews 37 (2023) https://www.sciencedirect.com/
science/article/pii/S0955470X23000459?via%3Dihub
accessed January 30, 2024.
- John W. Entwistle, et al., “Normothermic Regional
Perfusion: Ethical Issues in Thoracic Organ Donation,”
Journal of Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery 164 no.
1 (2022): 147-154.
- Uniform Determination of Death Act https://
www.uniformlaws.org/viewdocument/final-act49?CommunityKey=155faf5d-03c2-4027-99ba-ee4c9
9019d6c&tab=librarydocuments accessed January 29,
2024.
- Alex Manara, et al., “All Human Death Is Brain Death:
The Legacy of the Harvard Criteria,” Resuscitation 138
(2019): 210-212.
- Beatriz Dominguez-Gil, et al., “Expanding Controlled
Donation after the Circulatory Determination of Death:
Statement from an International Collaborative.” Intensive
Care Medicine, (2021) https://doi.org/10.1007/s00134-
020-06341-7 accessed January 26, 2024.
- John Paul II, The Address of the Holy Father John
Paul II to the 18th International Congress of the
Transplantation Society, August 29, 2000 https://www.
vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/speeches/2000/
jul-sep/documents/hf_jp-ii_spe_20000829_transplants.
html accessed January 10, 2024.
- The American Society of Anesthesiologists made this
statement on their website, and it is cited in journal
articles at https://www.asahq.org/standards-andguidelines/statement-on-controlled-organ-donationafter-circulatory-death . The URL is no longer valid. Last
accessed Summer, 2023. The current statement about
NRP on the website does not make this statement.
- John Paul II, Transplantation Society Address, 2000.
- Academy of Medical Royal Colleges, “A Code of Practice
for the Diagnosis and Confirmation of Death,” (2008):https://aomrc.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/2016/04/
Code_Practice_Confirmation_Diagnosis_Death_1008-4.pdf accessed January 30, 2024.
- Alex Manara, et al., “Maintaining the Permanence
Principle for Death During in Situ Normothermic Regional
Perfusion for Donation after Circulatory Death Organ
Recovery: A United Kingdom and Canadian Proposal,”
American Journal of Transplantation 20 (2020):2017–
2025.
- Dale Gardiner, et al., “Permanent Brain Arrest as the
Sole Criterion of Death in Systemic Circulatory Arrest,”
Anaesthesia 75 (2020): 1223–1228.
- James Bernat, et al., “How the Distinction between
“Irreversible” and “Permanent” Illuminates CirculatoryRespiratory Death Determination,” Journal of Medicine
and Philosophy 35 (2010): 242–255.
- Matthew DeCamp, et al., “Standards and Ethics Issues
in the Determination of Death: A Position Paper from
the American College of Physicians,” Annals of Internal
Medicine (September 2023) doi:10.7326/M23-1361
accessed September 7, 2023.
- David Greer, et al., “Pediatric and Adult Brain Death/
Death by Neurologic Criteria Consensus Guideline.
Report of the AAN Guidelines Subcommittee, AAP,
CNS, and SCCM,” Neurology 101 no.24 (2023):1-21.
doi:10.1212/WNL.0000000000207740
- National Catholic Bioethics Center, “Submission of the
NCBC and USCCB to the Uniform Determination of Death
Committee of the Uniform Law Commission,” July 12,
2023 https://www.usccb.org/resources/submissionncbc-and-usccb-uniform-determination-death-committeeuniform-law-commission accessed September 7, 2023.
- https://dictionary.cambridge.org/us/dictionary/english/
function accessed January 18, 2024.
- The author and the author’s colleagues have discussed
this matter with multiple procurement team surgeons.
- Impact of CMS Organ Procurement Organization
Certification Changes published online in The Alliance
Executive Insight Series (fall 2023) https://www.
organdonationalliance.org/insight/impact-of-cmsorgan-procurement-organization-certification-changes/
accessed January 18, 2024.